WWW.THESIS.XLIBX.INFO
FREE ELECTRONIC LIBRARY - Thesis, documentation, books
 
<< HOME
CONTACTS



Pages:   || 2 |

«By Gödel I Do Not Mean Schmidt JASON DAYLEY I n Naming and Necessity, Saul Kripke attacks the descriptivist theory of proper names made popular by ...»

-- [ Page 1 ] --

Aporia vol. 16 no. 2—2006

By Gödel I Do Not Mean Schmidt

JASON DAYLEY

I

n Naming and Necessity, Saul Kripke attacks the descriptivist theory of

proper names made popular by Gottlob Frege, Bertrand Russell, and

P.F. Strawson. Kripke proposes several examples that point out weaknesses in the descriptivist theory as well as a more accurate picture of how

names achieve reference to objects. Among Kripke's examples is a counterfactual situation in which Kurt Gödel does not produce the incompleteness theorem but fools the world into thinking that he has. There is some question in the descriptivist theory whether a person who only knows Gödel as the author of the incompleteness proof refers, using the name "Gödel," to the person Kurt Gödel or to the actual author of the incompleteness theorem. John Searle, in "Proper Names and Intentionality," responds on behalf of the descriptivists both to Kripke's better picture of naming and specifically to the Gödel example. While Searle believes that Kripke has mischaracterized the descriptivists and adopted their method into his own, Searle himself has misrepresented Kripke's argument and given a descriptivist answer that only strengthens Kripke's point against such theories. Consequently, Searle's reply to Kripke's Gödel example misunderstands the implications of this example for the descriptivist theory, and Searle fails to give an adequate reply.

Advocates of a descriptivist theory of proper names believe that names achieve reference by use of a definite description. There is some variety of opinions among these advocates as to how this occurs. Frege wrote that every name has an associated definite description that is the Jason Dayley is a senior majoring in philosophy with a minor in logic at Brigham Young University. After graduation in December 2006, he will attend law school.

2 JASON DAYLEY

manner or sense in which it refers to the intended object (Frege, "On Sense and Nominatum" 200). Russell wrote that names are merely placeholders or abbreviations of definite descriptions and that the denoting phrase, rather than the object itself, is the constituent of a sentence (Russell, "On Denoting" 492–493). Russell did allow that if an object is known by a direct acquaintance, its name may simply present the object named, but problems with this theory pushed him to later reduce the set of names that work in this way to ostensively defined sense data like "red here." So what we commonly call a name, at least for Russell's latter theory, is merely a disguised definite description.

The example of the name "Plato" may help to clarify the way names work according to these theories. "Plato" refers to an object because it contains or is the abbreviation of a definite description. "The man who was a student of Socrates and taught Aristotle," is such a definite description that seems to pick out the object we would normally want to refer to by the name "Plato." This definite description is the sense in which the name is used. A name may have more than one sense, but only one sense can be meant in any one use of the name. A descriptive sentence containing the name "Plato" asserts that what is referred to by the intended sense of this name has the properties indicated by the predicate of that sentence, or if the subject is predicated as the referent of a definite description, then the sentence asserts that the predicate description picks out the same object as the definite description which is the sense of the name used as the subject.

Take the sentence "Plato is my favorite philosopher." According to Frege's theory, this sentence seems to show that the sense of "Plato," "the man who was a student of Socrates and taught Aristotle," picks out the same object as the predicate description, "my favorite philosopher." Russell's theory makes this work more directly. The sentence, according to Russell, should be understood as "the object which was a man, learned from Socrates, and taught Aristotle, is the same object as my favorite philosopher." So, generally, Frege and Russell assert that a name serves only to pick out an object by means of an inherent definite description.

Strawson criticized Russell's understanding of how definite descriptions work, though he maintained a descriptivist theory of proper names.

Strawson clarified that a description itself does not refer, but the use of a

BY GÖDEL I DO NOT MEAN SCHMIDT 3

description by a person does (Strawson, “On Referring” 326–327). While Strawson says little about names specifically, his criticism of Russell seems to be relevant to the descriptivist theory. Since Strawson was a descriptivist, it follows from his use distinction of descriptions that names also do not refer. Only the use of a name by a person refers. The important point here is that for Strawson the definite description by which a name achieves reference is not part of the name, but is part of the intention of the speaker.

If my seven-year-old son were named Plato, it is not likely that my command "Plato! Come and pick up your toys" would be directed to the student of Socrates who in turn taught Aristotle. This idea, that the definite description associated with a name is a reflection of the speaker's intention, will be returned to in discussing Searle's response to Kripke.





Kripke attacks the descriptivists with a number of counterexamples;

one of which serves as the focus of this paper (Kripke, Naming and Necessity).1 Kurt Gödel is most often known for producing the incompleteness of arithmetic theorem. Following the descriptivist theory, when a person uses the name "Gödel" he is able to pick out a certain person by an implied use of the definite description "author of the incompleteness proof." When I write the sentence, "Gödel was a mathematician," I mean that the author of the incompleteness proof was a mathematician. It may seem obvious that the author of the incompleteness theorem was a mathematician, but if this is what is commonly known about Gödel then my original statement is just as obvious. In any case, the descriptivist theory's treatment of this situation seems to reflect my intention in using the sentence.

To show the problem with this picture, Kripke describes a hypothetical situation in which the definite description used picks out someone other than the person intended. Say, for example, that Gödel was a brilliant man who did everything a biography says he did, except that he did not create the incompleteness proof. Suppose instead that his brilliant though obscure friend Mr. Schmidt actually came up with the entire proof, 1 Kripke’s book will hereafter be cited by the author’s name followed by the page number.

2 There is a problem with circularity when the definite description associated with a name also contains a name (Kripke 81–82). For this reason, Kripke writes that a better example would be of a person who "actually states a certain theorem, which he attributes to Gödel as the discoverer" (Kripke 83). For the purpose of this paper, it should be understood that the name "the incompleteness proof" inside the denoting phrase associated with Gödel should really be replaced with Gödel's proof of arithmetic's incompleteness in its entirety.

4 JASON DAYLEY

only discussing the matter with Gödel. Before having a chance to show anyone else, Mr. Schmidt mysteriously vanishes and is never found. Gödel, who it turns out was not such a good friend, takes Schmidt's manuscript and publishes it as his own. Now, when I say "Gödel was a mathematician" and mean "the author of the incompleteness proof was a mathematician," do I actually mean to indicate that Schmidt, whom I have never heard of, was a mathematician? This may be the case if I am using the name and associated definite description in what Keith Donnellan called the referential use; that is, if I mean to say that whoever authored the incompleteness proof was a mathematician, but this is not always the case (Donnellan, “Reference and Defininte Descriptions” 285). A clearer example may be someone saying "I had Gödel's class at Princeton." Clearly this person does not mean she had a class from Schmidt; so, there is a problem which the descriptivist's must answer.

A descriptivist may respond to this apparent problem that the person, who was able to refer to Gödel directly rather than referentially, knew more about Gödel than just that he created the incompleteness proof.

Hence, she could have intended another definite description or only the person who fits most of the properties she associates with the name "Gödel." Rather than explain why a cluster of properties is no more consistent in referring than a single property, let us modify the example to someone who only knows of Gödel that he authored the incompleteness proof and that he was introduced to him once at a party.3 The day after the party this man may say to his wife, "Last night I was introduced to Gödel."

Superficially, he could mean, "Last night I was introduced to the author of the incompleteness proof," but he could not mean that last night he was introduced to Schmidt, whom he has never heard of and certainly never met. It may be objected that the reference does not hold in such situations because the description is not of a necessary property and should not be expected to work in counterfactual situations. However, it is undoubtable that such situations, i.e. those in which we are mistaken as to whom a description refers, occur in the actual world and we would merely have to find one to show that this objection cannot hold. Furthermore, it would be impossible to rationally believe that names refer using only necessary 3 Kripke discusses the cluster theory in his book (Kripke 64–68).

BY GÖDEL I DO NOT MEAN SCHMIDT 5

properties. Kripke admits that certain properties of a person are necessary such as the time in which they lived (Kripke 62), their parents, or their identity as a human (Kripke 46). Neither the time period of a person's life nor their identity as a human being could ever pick out a unique individual;4 hence, such descriptions could never explain how a name is able to refer directly to a unique individual. Perhaps if we gave the exact second of a person's being born or that person’s birth order relative to the person’s parents, i.e. second born of Michael and Susan Jones, we could pick out a unique individual by necessary properties, but surely we do not know such information about every person to whom we refer using a name.

One may object that a different type of definite description would solve the problem. For instance, the partygoer may refer to Gödel as "the man introduced to me as Gödel" rather than by his original knowledge of Gödel as "the author of the incompleteness proof," but this at best describes the picture Kripke gives for the way names work. The objector may say that by "Gödel" I mean "the man called Gödel," but this is blatantly circular and hence problematic (Kripke 72). If instead "Gödel" is to mean "the person whom I learned from an acquaintance is called Gödel," then this becomes an example of the picture Kripke gives. According to the alternative picture of naming given by Kripke, a person or object is ceremoniously given a name.5 It is only important here that there is a first use of the name in which it is given to an object. The name is then told to others by fixing the referent either by ostensive definition or by use of a definite description. So, the partygoer learns the name of a specific object, in this case a specific person, by being shown the reference, while in the original example the name was learned by being told it refers to the person who authored the incompleteness proof. In the first case, it seems obvious that the partygoer refers to a certain person whether or not he has any property other than being the man to whom I was introduced. In the second case, the description used to fix the reference could have been faulty, but I still 4 While it may be that during a single second, or whatever unit of time one takes to be atomic, only a single individual was born, it is epistemically impossible that anyone, even one present at the delivery, could know this and use it for the purpose of referring. Since reference occurs as a person uses a name or description, and no one could ever know they were picking out someone uniquely by specifying the second they were born, the objection that unique reference by time of birth may be possible if one were specific enough is erroneous.

5 While Kripke uses the image of a ceremony, it is unclear wheter he means more than ostensibly assigning an arbitrary name.

6 JASON DAYLEY

understand Gödel to be Gödel and not Schmidt. Suppose I learned the name "Gödel" from a Mr. Smith, who was introduced to the man by those who named him, his parents.6 Smith knows that I am not acquainted with Gödel's parents but that I know something about math, so Smith states the result of the incompleteness theorem and then that it was Gödel who proved this. If we are all mistaken and Schmidt actually authored the proof, then the name still refers, through a causal chain, back to Gödel himself.

This picture of how names work shows why a person, who was told that Gödel is going to give a lecture and who only knows Gödel as the author of the incompleteness proof, does not expect upon going to the lecture to hear from Schmidt.

Searle asserts in "Proper Names and Intentionality," that Kripke has mischaracterized the descriptivist theory and that his picture seems to only work in a descriptivist way. Searle clarifies that the question these theories are trying to answer is, "How in the utterance of a name does the speaker succeed in referring to an object?" (Searle, “Proper Names and Intentionality” 309).7 Searle goes on to characterize the descriptivist answer: "The answer given by the descriptivist is that the speaker refers to the object because and only because the object satisfies the Intentional content associated with the name" (Searle 309). Searle seems to believe, along with what was inferred earlier from Strawson, that names are able to refer to objects by use of a description which the name's speaker has in mind as he uses the name. In other words, when I say the name 'Gödel," it is my intention to speak of the person who authored the incompleteness theorem, and so I am able to refer to that man with use of this name.



Pages:   || 2 |


Similar works:

«I. THE TRAGEDY AT WACO: AN ANNIHILATION OF AUTONOMY In early 1993 there was played out on the plains of Texas near Waco the gravest church-state confrontation since the federal vendetta against the Mormons in the second decade after the Civil War. It is chronicled here at some length because of its implications for the theme of this volume. In a rare prodigy of ostensible selfexamination, two departments of the federal government issued lengthy reports to the public on the events and their part...»

«By email only CCL and REGO Manager Ofgem 9 Millbank London SW1P 3GE th 19 June 2015 Dear Sir/Madam, Consultation on market coupling and Levy Exemption Certificates and call for evidence on wider impacts RWE npower Group plc holding company for supply licences welcomes the opportunity to respond to the Ofgem consultation on market coupling and Levy Exemption Certificates and the call for evidence on wider impacts. Please find our response enclosed and a few high level comments below. We believe...»

«A Study of the Relationship Between Moral Maturity and Respondent’s Self-Rated Leadership Style Charles R. Salter Schreiner University Mary H. Harris Cabrini University Mark Woodhull Schreiner University Jay McCormack Schreiner University The study of moral development and the effects it has on decision making have garnered a good deal of interest in the last thirty years. Rest, Thoma, and Narvaez (1999e) discuss the cognitive schemas associated with the different levels of moral development...»

«i Crisis COMMUNICATION ii Expression of thanks The authors would like to thank the following people for their much appreciated help: Bob Bellafiore, George Bogdanich, Lori C Booker, Myra J Borshoff, Barbara Casey, Colette Cornelissens, Lars Dagerholt, Susan A Davis, Ray D Eisenbrenner, Thor Erling Lund, Pamela D Evans, Amanda Farek, Michael Fineman, Rick French, Acácio Gomes, Bobbie Goodwin, Christian Hannestad, Eric Hess, Peggy Hubble, Raphael Hyslop, Carol Javaudin, Gwinavere Johnston, David...»

«Report on the school evaluation Name of head of school Mr. Andrew Wood Name of school IB school code IS Hout Bay 003487 Date IB programme 18-03-2013 PYP Student ages in which all students are 3-4 4-5 5-6 6-7 7-8 8-9 9-10 10-11 11-12 engaged in PYP Dear Head of school Thank you for completing the self-study process for programme evaluation. The aim of programme evaluation is for the IB to ensure on a regular basis that the standards and practices of the programme are being maintained. The IB is...»

«Ulrich Schneekloth & Hans Werner Wahl (Hrsg.) Möglichkeiten und Grenzen selbständiger Lebensführung in privaten Haushalten (MuG III) Repräsentativbefunde und Vertiefungsstudien zu häuslichen Pflegearrangements, Demenz und professionellen Versorgungsangeboten Integrierter Abschlussbericht im Auftrag des Bundesministeriums für Familie, Senioren, Frauen und Jugend München, März 2005 Herausgeber Ulrich Schneekloth (TNS Infratest Sozialforschung, München) Hans Werner Wahl (Deutsches Zentrum...»

«THE WORLD BANK Migration and Development Brief Migration and Remittances Team, Development Prospects Group April 13, 2015 Migration and Remittances: Recent Developments and Outlook* Special Topic: Financing for Development  Using newly available census data, the stock of international migrants is estimated at 247 million in 2013, significantly larger than the previous estimate of 232 million, and is expected to surpass 250 million in 2015.  Migrants’ remittances to developing countries...»

«Description Logics for Matchmaking of Services Javier Gonzalez-Castillo, David Trastour, Claudio Bartolini Trusted E-Services Laboratory HP Laboratories Bristol HPL-2001-265 October 30th, 2001* E-mail: javgon@hplb.hp.com, david_trastour@hp.com, claudio_bartolini@hp.com Matchmaking is an important aspect of E-Commerce interactions. The current trend in B2B E-Commerce automation is towards complex interactions for service provision. In this context, matchmaking services require rich and flexible...»

«Fire and Ice Sermon Series http://www.puritansermons.com/ Thomas Hooker And The Doctrine Of Conversion by Iain H. Murray Part 1: Beholding the Majesty of God1 A mong the multitude of Puritan books which have survived the 17th Century The Pilgrim’s Progress by John Bunyan has often been regarded as one of the few which can be called uncontroversial. It is an incorrect judgment, for Part I of Bunyan’s classic, published in 1678, describes the process by which Pilgrim became a Christian in...»

«The Shift from Defined Benefit to Defined Contribution Pension Plans Implications for Asset Allocation and Risk Management John Broadbent Domestic Markets Department Reserve Bank of Australia Sydney, NSW 2000 Michael Palumbo Division of Research and Statistics Federal Reserve Board 20th and C Streets, NW Washington DC 20551 and Elizabeth Woodman Financial Markets Department Bank of Canada 234 Wellington, Ottawa Ontario K1A 0G9 December 2006 Prepared for a Working Group on Institutional Inve...»

«Auditor independence in a private Working Paper No. 1/2007 firm and low litigation risk setting December 2007 Revised April 2009 Ole-Kristian Hope and John Christian Langli © Ole-Kristian Hope and John Christian Langli 2009. All rights reserved. Short sections of text, not to exceed two paragraphs, may be quoted without explicit permission, provided that full credit, including © notice, is given to the source. This paper can be downloaded without charge from the CCGR website...»

«UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA STEVEN AFTERGOOD, : : Plaintiff, : Civil Action No.: 01-2524 (RMU) : v. : Document Nos.: 24, 26, 28 :CENTRAL INTELLIGENCE AGENCY, : : Defendant. : MEMORANDUM OPINION DENYING THE PLAINTIFF’S MOTION FOR SUMMARY JUDGMENT; DENYING THE PLAINTIFF’S MOTION TO STRIKE; GRANTING THE DEFENDANT’S CROSS-MOTION FOR SUMMARY JUDGMENT I. INTRODUCTION This matter comes before the court on the plaintiff’s motion for summary judgment and the...»





 
<<  HOME   |    CONTACTS
2016 www.thesis.xlibx.info - Thesis, documentation, books

Materials of this site are available for review, all rights belong to their respective owners.
If you do not agree with the fact that your material is placed on this site, please, email us, we will within 1-2 business days delete him.